Chance News 21: Difference between revisions
mNo edit summary |
|||
(106 intermediate revisions by 5 users not shown) | |||
Line 1: | Line 1: | ||
September 28, 2006 to November 1, 2006 | |||
<blockquote> | ==Quotation== | ||
<div align=right> | |||
<blockquote>You may end up with a different math, but you're entitled to your math. I'm entitled to THE math.</blockquote> | |||
[http://www. | <div align=right>Karl Rove<br> | ||
[http://www.npr.org/templates/story/story.php?storyId=6376549 NPR All things considered, October 24, 2006]</div> | |||
Note: Karl Rove is the White House Deputy Chief of Staff. He was comparing the 68 polls a week that he reads with those that moderator Robert Siegle reads from the media. | |||
==Forsooth== | ==Forsooth== | ||
These two Forsooths are from the October RRS NEWS. | |||
---- | ---- | ||
<blockquote>Long-term, serious smokers have a 50% chance of dying. | <blockquote>Long-term, serious smokers have a 50% chance of dying. | ||
Line 27: | Line 27: | ||
20 April 2006</div> | 20 April 2006</div> | ||
</blockquote> | </blockquote> | ||
---- | |||
==A car talk puzzle revisited== | ==A car talk puzzle revisited== | ||
In Chance News 20 we asked for the answer to the following car talk puzzle (Week | In Chance News 20 we asked for the answer to the following car talk puzzle (Week | ||
of 08-23-04) | of 08-23-04): | ||
<blockquote>The bullet holes were all over the place on the R.A.F. planes -- in the wings | <blockquote>The bullet holes were all over the place on the R.A.F. planes -- in the wings | ||
Line 38: | Line 39: | ||
missions?</blockquote> | missions?</blockquote> | ||
Car | Car Talk gave the following answer: | ||
<blockquote> A nameless mathematician crawled underneath the planes and looked at where the | <blockquote> A nameless mathematician crawled underneath the planes and looked at where the | ||
Line 52: | Line 53: | ||
Reader Mike Cox wrote us that the mathematician was the famous statistician | Reader Mike Cox wrote us that the mathematician was the famous statistician | ||
Abraham Wald | Abraham Wald and gave the following references for Wald's work: "A Method of Estimating Plane Vulnerability Based on Damage of Survivors, Abraham Wald, Center for Naval Analyses, 423, July 1980. and "Abraham Wald's Work on Aircraft Survivability, Marc Mangel;Fancisco J. Samaniego, ''Journal of the American Statistical Association'',Vol. 79, No. 386, pp. 259-267. | ||
Estimating Plane | |||
The Car Talk story was discussed in "A selection of selection anomalies," ''Chance Magazine'', Vol. 11, No. 2, Spring 1998, pp. 3-8, Howard Wainer, Samuel Palmer, and Eric T. Bradlow and we reviewed this article in [http://www.dartmouth.edu/~chance/chance_news/recent_news/chance_news_7.05.html#selection%20anomalies Chance news 7.05] so we should have remembered this story. It is also discussed in Howard Wainer's recent book "Graphic Discovery: A Trout in the Milk and Other Visual Adventures" and on the [http://digitalroam.typepad.com/digital_roam/2006/03/the_hole_story_.html Digital Roan Blog]. | |||
[http://digitalroam.typepad.com/digital_roam/2006/03/the_hole_story_.html Digital Roan | |||
Wald | When we looked the Wald references we were surprised to find that they did not include the Car Talk story or the sketches often mentioned in discussing this story. However, as the title suggests, Wald did discuss ways to assess the chance of a plane being shot down by hits at various parts of a plane, so it is plausible that he might have recommended armor plating only the unhit areas that the returning planes had in common. If anyone knows a reference where he made this recommendation we would ask that you let us know about this. However as a wise man said: "Facts shouldn't get in the way of a good story." | ||
Here is a brief sketch of what Wald does in the Center for Naval Analyses report. Wald assumes that we have the following data for planes participating in combat: | |||
(1) The total number N of planes participating in combat. | |||
(2) For any integer i (i = 0,1,2,...) the number of planes that received exactly i hits but have not been downed, i.e., have returned from combat. | |||
The data in (2) is an example of missing data since the corresponding information is not known for the planes that do not return. | |||
Wald assumes that the probability that a plane will be shot down does not depend on the number of previous non-destructive hits. In his first chapter he shows how, despite the missing data, we can estimate the probability that a plane is shot down by the i'th hit. In a later chapter he divides the plane into four equal areas and shows how to estimate the probability that a plane is downed by a single hit for each of the four areas. This allows him to compare the vulnerability of these areas. He illustrates this by the following example: | |||
400 planes go on a bombing mission, 359 return. Of these, 240 were not hit, 68 had one it, 29 had two hits, 12 had three hits, and 10 had four hits. | |||
His analysis shows that the probabilities of being downed by a single hit in each of the four areas is given in the following table: | |||
<center> | <center> | ||
<table width=" | <table width="55%" border="1"> | ||
<tr> | <tr> | ||
<td> | <td>Part</td> | ||
<td>Probability of being downed by a single hit.</td> | |||
<td> | |||
</tr> | </tr> | ||
<tr> | <tr> | ||
<td> | <td>Entire plane</td> | ||
<td><div align="center">.15</div></td> | |||
<td><div align="center"> | |||
</tr> | </tr> | ||
<tr> | <tr> | ||
<td> | <td>Engines</td> | ||
<td><div align="center">.39</div></td> | |||
<td><div align="center"> | |||
</tr> | </tr> | ||
<tr> | <tr> | ||
<td> | <td>Fuselage</td> | ||
<td><div align="center">.05</div></td> | |||
<td><div align="center"> | |||
</tr> | </tr> | ||
<tr> | <tr> | ||
<td> | <td>Fuel system</td> | ||
<td><div align="center">.15</div></td> | |||
<td><div align="center"> | |||
</tr> | </tr> | ||
<tr> | <tr> | ||
<td | <td>Other parts</td> | ||
<td><div align="center">.02</div></td> | |||
<td><div align="center"> | |||
</tr> | </tr> | ||
</table> | </table> | ||
</center> | </center> | ||
Wald writes: | |||
<blockquote> Thus for the observed data of this hypothetical example, the engine area is the most vulnerable in the sense that a hit there is most likely to down the plane. The fuselage has a relatively low vulnerability. </blockquote> | |||
Wald remarks that this method can be used as a guide for locating protection armor and can be used to make a prediction of the esitimated loss in future missions. | |||
The article by Mangel and Samaniego gives a good account of Wald's work and shows how to apply more recent statistical techniques to Wald's problems. Their article is followed by interesting comments by James Berger which in turn is followed by a rejoinder from Mangel and Samaniego. This rejoinder includes the following interesting comment: | |||
< | <blockquote>A number of people have asked whether Wald's work has actually been used. We do not know whether it was used during World War II, although it was produced early enough in the war to have been available. We do know that during the Vietnam War, analysts at the Operations Evaluation Group of the Center for Naval Analyses used Wald's techniques to study the survivability of the A-4 aircraft. Their analysis led to structural modifications that improved the A-4's survivability. </blockquote> | ||
Submitted by Laurie Snell | |||
==Probability theory is not all that useful== | ==Probability theory is not all that useful== | ||
[http://www.johnkay.com/in_action/457 Don’t box yourself in when making decisions], John Kay, Financial Times, 22 August 2006. | [http://www.johnkay.com/in_action/457 Don’t box yourself in when making decisions], John Kay, Financial Times, 22 August 2006. | ||
In this article, [http://www.johnkay.com/ John Kay], a weekly columnist for the [http://www.ft.com Financial Times], outlines a variation on the [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/ | In this article, [http://www.johnkay.com/ John Kay], a weekly columnist for the [http://www.ft.com Financial Times], outlines a variation on the [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Monty_Hall_Problem Monty Hall problem], | ||
to highlight that human minds are not well adapted to dealing with issues of probability. | to highlight that human minds are not well adapted to dealing with issues of probability. | ||
Line 269: | Line 142: | ||
===Questions=== | ===Questions=== | ||
* Kay claims that 'the message of both the original Monty Hall problem and of this one is that, even in very simple cases, it is impossible to be certain that a particular mathematical representation of a real problem is a correct description. ... For people in business who rely on models and for people in financial services who must choose between boxes with uncertain contents every day, that is a disturbing conclusion.' Do you agree with his views? If yes, what might it imply for the teaching of probability? | * Kay claims that 'the message of both the original Monty Hall problem and of this one is that, even in very simple cases, it is impossible to be certain that a particular mathematical representation of a real problem is a correct description. ... For people in business who rely on models and for people in financial services who must choose between boxes with uncertain contents every day, that is a disturbing conclusion.' Do you agree with his views? If yes, what might it imply for the teaching of probability? | ||
* Do you agree with Kay's comment that many people dislike the propect of losing £50 more than they like the prospect of gaining £100? This touches on the topic of [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Behavioral_finance behavioural economics], | * Do you agree with Kay's comment that many people dislike the propect of losing £50 more than they like the prospect of gaining £100? This touches on the topic of [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Behavioral_finance behavioural economics,] in particular loss aversion according to [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Prospect_theory prospect theory] - given a choice between risky outcomes, we suffer about two times as much for losses as we enjoy comparable gains. This has become a popular topic for study in recent years, especially since [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Daniel_Kahneman Daniel Kahneman] was awarded a [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Nobel_Prize_in_Economics Nobel prize in economics] 'for having integrated insights from psychological research into economic science, especially concerning human judgment and decision-making under uncertainty'. Does this comment help to resolve this paradox or is it irrelevant? | ||
* Repeating the game many times, increases the chance of achieving positive expected payoff. What hidden assumptions are being made here? (If a few more zeros were added to the payoffs, would your attitude be different?) Is there any merit in his 'fallacy of large numbers'? What is it about the 99th attempt that makes it different to the first attempt? | * Repeating the game many times, increases the chance of achieving positive expected payoff. What hidden assumptions are being made here? (If a few more zeros were added to the payoffs, would your attitude be different?) Is there any merit in his 'fallacy of large numbers'? What is it about the 99th attempt that makes it different to the first attempt? | ||
* To benefit from the irrationality of the equity premium, Kay suggests to stop looking at share prices so often, so, in the long run, you will get the benefit of the higher return without the pain of observing volatility. Is there any merit in this suggestion? Does it suggest that rational investors, facing the same problem but with different time horizons, can logically reach very different conclusions? | * To benefit from the irrationality of the equity premium, Kay suggests to stop looking at share prices so often, so, in the long run, you will get the benefit of the higher return without the pain of observing volatility. Is there any merit in this suggestion? Does it suggest that rational investors, facing the same problem but with different time horizons, can logically reach very different conclusions? | ||
===Further reading=== | ===Further reading=== | ||
* The topic in this article (and the next one) is often referred to as the envelope paradox(s) which have been discussed in | * The topic in this article (and the next one) is often referred to as the envelope paradox(s) which have been discussed in previous issues of Chance News going back to 1992. For example, [http://www.dartmouth.edu/~chance/chance_news/recent_news/chance_news_9.09.html#item10 Chance News 9.09 ] in the discussion qustions says 'A much more mysterious envelope paradox is the following: I put two distinct numbers a and b in an envelope. You pick one of the numbers at random. Show that you can decide if you have the bigger or smaller number with a probability greater than 1/2 of being correct. The envelope paradoxes are discussed in [http://www.dartmouth.edu/~chance/teaching_aids/books_articles/probability_book/Chapter4.pdf Chapter 4, examples 4.28 and 4.29] of the on-line probability book [http://www.dartmouth.edu/~chance/teaching_aids/books_articles/probability_book/book.html Introduction to Probability], Charles M. Grinstead and J. Laurie Snell, American Mathematical Society. | ||
* There are several webpages devoted to [http://www.google.co.uk/search?hl=en&q=envelope+paradox&meta= this difficult paradox]. For example, [http://www.anc.ed.ac.uk/~amos/doubleswap.html Amos Storkey] offers a Bayesian solution and logician Raymond Smullyan claims that the paradox can be [http://members.aol.com/kiekeben/envelope.html restated without involving probability] in his book [http://tinyurl.com/ruksm Satan, Cantor and Infinity and Other Mind-boggling Puzzles.] He does this by proving two contradictory propositions: | * There are several webpages devoted to [http://www.google.co.uk/search?hl=en&q=envelope+paradox&meta= this difficult paradox]. For example, [http://www.anc.ed.ac.uk/~amos/doubleswap.html Amos Storkey] offers a Bayesian solution and logician [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Raymond_Smullyan Raymond Smullyan] claims that the paradox can be [http://members.aol.com/kiekeben/envelope.html restated without involving probability] in his book [http://tinyurl.com/ruksm Satan, Cantor and Infinity and Other Mind-boggling Puzzles.] He does this by proving two contradictory propositions: | ||
** "Proposition 1. The amount that you will gain, if you do gain, is greater than the amount you will lose, if you do lose. | ** "Proposition 1. The amount that you will gain, if you do gain, is greater than the amount you will lose, if you do lose. | ||
** "Proposition 2. The amounts are the same." | ** "Proposition 2. The amounts are the same." | ||
Line 282: | Line 155: | ||
==Intuition is better than maths== | ==Intuition is better than maths== | ||
[http://www.johnkay.com/in_action/458 The maths may be simple but intuition is more | [http://www.johnkay.com/in_action/458 The maths may be simple but intuition is more usefull], John Kay, Financial Times 29 August 2006. | ||
In the two-box problem (see the [http://chance.dartmouth.edu/chancewiki/index.php/Chance_News_21#Probability_theory_is_not_all_that_useful 'Probability theory is not all that useful'] article above), that puzzle offers you a choice of two boxes, one containing more money than the other. Once you have made a decision, you are shown what is in your preferred box. Do you stick with your original choice, or switch? | In the two-box problem (see the [http://chance.dartmouth.edu/chancewiki/index.php/Chance_News_21#Probability_theory_is_not_all_that_useful 'Probability theory is not all that useful'] article above), that puzzle offers you a choice of two boxes, one containing more money than the other. Once you have made a decision, you are shown what is in your preferred box. Do you stick with your original choice, or switch? | ||
Line 299: | Line 172: | ||
He also suggests choosing a threshold in the range of sums of money that would make a real difference to you. For example, if £20,000 would not transform your life but £50,000 would, then go for £50,000. | He also suggests choosing a threshold in the range of sums of money that would make a real difference to you. For example, if £20,000 would not transform your life but £50,000 would, then go for £50,000. | ||
While | While admitting that the logic behind this solution is not straightforward but he claims that, intuitively, it makes sense. He claims that in real-life problems we typically adopt the principle of being realistic while looking for something that will make a difference. | ||
In the version of the two-box problem, in the previous Chance article, where you had the additional information that one box contained twice as much money as the other, there seemed always to be an argument for switching; the potential gain is always twice the seemingly equally likely potential loss. But this conclusion is wrong. Once more, intuition runs ahead of our mathematical understanding, he concludes. | In the version of the two-box problem, in the previous Chance article, where you had the additional information that one box contained twice as much money as the other, there seemed always to be an argument for switching; the potential gain is always twice the seemingly equally likely potential loss. But this conclusion is wrong. Once more, intuition runs ahead of our mathematical understanding, he concludes. | ||
Line 308: | Line 181: | ||
Submitted by John Gavin | Submitted by John Gavin | ||
==Comments on Kay's articles== | |||
In his first article, Kay discusses the infamous two-box or two-envelope problem. This problem has a long history which you can find at Wikipedia [http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Two_envelopes_problem here]. | |||
Here is the way this problem is described in the Grinstead-Snell [http://www.dartmouth.edu/~chance/teaching_aids/books_articles/probability_book/book.html probability book]. Two-envelopes each contain a certain amount of money. One envelope is given to Ali and the other to Baba and they are told that one envelope contains twice as much money as the other. However, neither knows who has the larger prize. Before anyone has opened their envelope, Ali is asked if she would like to trade her envelope with Baba. | |||
She reasons as follows: Assume that the amount in my envelope is x. If I switch, | |||
I will end up with x/2 with probability 1/2, and 2x with probability 1/2. If I were | |||
given the opportunity to play this game many times, and if I were to switch each time, | |||
I would, on average, get | |||
<center><math> \frac {1} {2}\frac{x}{2} + \frac{1}{2}2x = \frac{5}{4}x.</math></center> | |||
This is greater than my average winnings if I didn't switch. | |||
Of course, Baba is presented with the same opportunity and reasons in the same way | |||
to conclude that he too would like to switch. So they switch and each thinks that | |||
his/her net worth just went up by 25%. | |||
Since neither has yet opened any envelope, this process can be | |||
repeated and so again they switch. Now they are back with their original | |||
envelopes and yet they think that their fortune has increased 25% twice. | |||
By this reasoning, they could convince themselves that by repeatedly switching the | |||
envelopes, they could become arbitrarily wealthy. Clearly, something is wrong with | |||
the above reasoning, but where is the mistake? | |||
Well, for one thing we have interpreted <math> \frac{5}{4}x</math> as the expected amount Ali will have if she switches. But x is a random variable, not a number, as would be required for an expected value. | |||
To correctly compute the expected value we have to know something about how the numbers x, and 2x were put in the envelopes. Assume that we toss a coin. If heads turns up x is put in envelope 1 and 2x in envelope 2. if tails turn up 2x is put in envelope 1 and x in envelope 2. This satisfies the condition that Ali and Bali have no idea which number they have but they know that one number is twice the other number. Then since each envelope has x or 2x as the result of the toss of a coin the expected amount in either envelope is 1/2(x) + 1/2(2x) = 3/2x. So why switch? | |||
In the second article Kay seems to be considering the same problem but his description fits better with the second envelope paradox which is credited to Thomas Cover: "Pick the largest number" in Communication and Computation, T. Cover and B. Gopinath, eds., Springer-Verlag, New York, 1987, p. 152. | |||
In this problem you are given 2 envelopes in each of which there are a number, and these numbers are different.. You are asked to choose one of the envelopes and tell if you think you have the smaller or the larger of the two numbers. It would seem that you could not do better than having a 50% chance of being correct but the surprising thing is that you can do better. | |||
To do this you choose a number according to a normal distribution with mean 0 or 1. Actually any distribution would do as long as all numbers are possible. Cover calls this number the ''splitting number'' T. | |||
If the number you chose was less than T then you say that you have the smaller number. If it is greater than T you say that you have the bigger number. Then you can show that if T is between the two numbers in the envelope you are sure to be correct and if not you still have a 50% chance of being correct. Since there is a positive probability that T will be between the two numbers you have a greater than 50% chance of being correct. | |||
Kay has the right idea for the solution to this problem but he chooses a specific number for T so he will not be able to be right with probability greater than .5 if the numbers were put in such a way that they must be bigger than T. | |||
Returning to the original problem, recall that Ali was allowed to what number was in her box. Thus while she cannot get a 25% increase by switching, by using Cover's strategy she can decide whether to switch or not in a way that will give her better than a 50% chance of ending up with 2x as Kay suggests in his second article. | |||
Submitted by Laurie Snell. | |||
==You're Only as Old As You Think You Are== | ==You're Only as Old As You Think You Are== | ||
Line 354: | Line 269: | ||
==The odds of dying== | ==The odds of dying== | ||
[http://www.nsc.org/lrs/statinfo/odds.htm What are the odds of dying?], (US) | [http://www.nsc.org/lrs/statinfo/odds.htm What are the odds of dying?], The (US) National Safety Council website.<br> | ||
Ways to Go, National Geographic, Siobhan Roth, August 2006.<br> | Ways to Go, National Geographic, Siobhan Roth, August 2006.<br> | ||
Recent statistics from the National Safety Council reveal the most likely way to die, over the lifetime of a US resident. | Recent statistics from the National Safety Council reveal the most likely way to die, over the lifetime of a US resident. | ||
So this article's objective is to answer commonly-asked questions from the media such as, <em>what are the odds of being killed by lightning?</em> or <em>what are the chances of dying in a plane crash?</em> | So this article's objective is to answer commonly-asked questions from the media such as, <em>what are the odds of being killed by lightning?</em> or <em>what are the chances of dying in a plane crash?</em> | ||
For example, motorbike riding is more risky than playing with fireworks. | It includes common causes of death, like car accidents, as well as large scale catastrophes, such as earthquakes. For example, motorbike riding is more risky than playing with fireworks. | ||
[[Image:Odds_dying.jpg|frame|left|National Geographic magazine's August 2006 issue features this <em>Ways to Go</em> chart based on the National Safety Council's <em>Odds of Dying</em> statistics.]] | [[Image:Odds_dying.jpg|frame|left|National Geographic magazine's August 2006 issue features this <em>Ways to Go</em> chart based on the National Safety Council's <em>Odds of Dying</em> statistics.]] | ||
Line 367: | Line 281: | ||
===Questions=== | ===Questions=== | ||
* The National Safety Council website presents the data in [http://www.nsc.org/lrs/statinfo/odds.htm tabular] as well as graphical form. Which form of presentation do you think makes it easier to interpret the data? | * The National Safety Council website presents the data in [http://www.nsc.org/lrs/statinfo/odds.htm tabular] as well as graphical form. Which form of presentation do you think makes it easier to interpret the data? | ||
* In [http://chance.dartmouth.edu/chancewiki/index.php/Chance_News_20 the previous edition on Chance] | * In [http://chance.dartmouth.edu/chancewiki/index.php/Chance_News_20 the previous edition on Chance,] a similar article, [http://chance.dartmouth.edu/chancewiki/index.php/Chance_News_20#Risk_perceptions <em>Risk perceptions</em>] ranked different ways of dying in tabular form. Is a ranked table easier to read? Is it always more appropriate for this kind of data? | ||
* In the graph | * In the graph below, the probabilities appear to be proportional to the area of the circles. Is a two-dimensional, area-based scale appropriate to display on one-dimensional data like probabilities? Why use circles? | ||
* The National Safety Council website states that these odds are statistical averages over the whole U.S. population and do not necessarily reflect the chances of death for a particular person from a particular external cause. What factors might cause an individual's odds to deviate from the average? | * The National Safety Council website states that these odds are statistical averages over the whole U.S. population and do not necessarily reflect the chances of death for a particular person from a particular external cause. What factors might cause an individual's odds to deviate from the average? | ||
* The odds are based on data from 2003. Why might the odds change more over time for some categories more than others? | * The odds are based on data from 2003. Why might the odds change more over time for some categories more than others? | ||
Line 394: | Line 308: | ||
</blockquote> | </blockquote> | ||
Following comments from the public, the author later supplemented the original Death and Taxes graph with a simplier graph showing mandatory spending as well, which adds some perspective. | Following comments from the public, the author later supplemented the original Death and Taxes graph with a simplier graph (shown below) showing mandatory spending as well, which adds some perspective. | ||
[[Image:totalBudget.jpg|400px|thumb|left|Graphic of the total budget emphasising the entitlement programs which are excluded from the 'Death and Taxes' graph, by Jesse Bachman.]] | [[Image:totalBudget.jpg|400px|thumb|left|Graphic of the total budget emphasising the entitlement programs which are excluded from the 'Death and Taxes' graph, by Jesse Bachman.]] | ||
===Questions=== | ===Questions=== | ||
* Assuming you can work with the [http://thebudgetgraph.comon-line on-line version], in order to zoom in, does the graph put the data into perspective, especially the complexity and inter-connectedness of the various items? For example, how does the national debt compare to other items? Does [http://thebudgetgraph.com/forums/index.php?topic=6.0 the total budget] | * Assuming you can work with the [http://thebudgetgraph.comon-line on-line version], in order to zoom in, does the graph put the data into perspective, especially the complexity and inter-connectedness of the various items? For example, how does the national debt compare to other items? Does [http://thebudgetgraph.com/forums/index.php?topic=6.0 the total budget] shown in the second graph offer a more informative perspective because it is less granular than the first graph? | ||
* Is the area of each node proportional to the magnitude of that item? What alternative relationships might be used to better visualise this information? | * Is the area of each node proportional to the magnitude of that item? What alternative relationships might be used to better visualise this information? | ||
* Do the various images within the graph improve its appearance or distract from the underlying data? Can you think of other ways to further improve the graph? | * Do the various images within the graph improve its appearance or distract from the underlying data? Can you think of other ways to further improve the graph? | ||
Line 406: | Line 321: | ||
===Futher reading=== | ===Futher reading=== | ||
* You can [http://www.thebudgetgraph.com/buy.html buy a poster] ($24 plus $4.95 shipping to anywhere in the US) or send one to the US congress for ten dollars. | * You can [http://www.thebudgetgraph.com/buy.html buy a poster] ($24 plus $4.95 shipping to anywhere in the US) or send one to the US congress for ten dollars. | ||
* [http://www.nigelholmes.com/motion/index.htm# This impressive animated film] by graphic designer [http://www.nigelholmes.com Nigel Holmes] describes the relative sizes of the US surplus and debt. | |||
* See [http://chance.dartmouth.edu/chancewiki/index.php/Chance_News_39#Death_and_taxes_-_2009_edition this Chance News article] for links to the latest (2009) graph. | |||
Submitted by John Gavin. | Submitted by John Gavin. | ||
==Alzheimer's== | |||
The medical moral of the story is simple: stay healthy so you don't need drugs. The statistical moral of the study is two-fold: (1) go to the original source instead of relying on what journalists write and (2) make sure that the right experiment is being done. The New England Journal of Medicine article of October 12, 2006 (Volume 355: 1525-1538 Number 15) entitled "Effectiveness of Atypical Antipsychotic Drugs in Patients with Alzheimer's Disease" received a fair amount of puzzling press review. The AP dispatch said "Symptoms did improve in about 30 percent of patients taking the drugs, as well as in 21 percent of those getting a placebo, partly because symptoms can naturally wax and wane." With 421 patients in the study and ignoring multiple comparisons (three drugs and a placebo), a quick calculation yields a p-value of .032 which is less than the magical .05 so it would seem that statistical significance was achieved. Yet, regarding clinical significance, the AP headline was "Anti-psychotic drugs don't ease dementia." Likewise, the headline for HealthDay's Amanda Gardner says "Antipsychotics No Better Than Placebo For Alzheimer's Patients." The headline for Denise Gellene's article in the Los Angeles Times was "Alzheimer's antipsychotic drugs 'are not the answer for most,' report says." | |||
It turns out that while 421 patients were enrolled in 42 different sites (!), 82% quit their medications due to lack of efficacy, intolerability and other reasons; in short, these powerful drugs have unpleasant side effects such as death. According to an accompanying editorial in the NEJM by Jason Karlawish, this clinical trial is the right experiment as opposed to previous clinical trials involving drugs for Alzheimer's. Those studies have outcomes which "are measured at multiple time points" accruing "a large volume of data." These approaches increase "the likelihood that any change measured will be statistically, though not necessarily clinically, significant. Clearly, these designs are particularly valuable to companies seeking an FDA label or reprints of reports to distribute to clinicians." | |||
Karlawish writes, "The primary end point in the study by Schneider et al. is an accurate reflection of a clinical event: the decision to change treatment because the patient's condition is worsening or not improving sufficiently." | |||
===Discussion=== | |||
1. The NEJM article had 13 authors, 12 of whom listed "potential conflicts of interest." The only one not listed as having a potential conflict of interest was the person without a M.D. or Ph.D. degree. Speculate what this implies. | |||
2. Define statistical significance. Define clinical significance. Does one imply the other? | |||
3. Despite the negative results of this clinical trial, because some patients benefited, the lead author said, "The message from this study cannot be that the drugs are not useful." Is this a scientific or a religious belief? | |||
4. All of the above refers to "Phase I." "Phase II" was not reported on in this article. In Phase II, those patients still willing to be randomly assigned "under double-blind conditions to receive one of the antipsychotic drugs to which they were not initially assigned" or to receive a drug not studied in Phase I. Why is this a good idea statistically? Why might this not be such a good idea for a patient? | |||
Submitted by Paul Alper. | |||
==The human cost of war== | |||
[http://www.economist.com/world/africa/displaystory.cfm?story_id=8038059 Calculating casualties - The human cost of war in Iraq], The Economist, Oct 12th 2006. | |||
A recent statistical [http://www.thelancet.com/journals/lancet/article/PIIS0140673606694919/fulltext study in the Lancet], a UK medical journal, claims that many more Iraqis have died in recent years than was previously thought, over 650,000 excess deaths. This is a follow-up study to a 2004 Lancet article on the same topic that was [http://www.dartmouth.edu/~chance/chance_news/current_news/current.html#item7 previously discussed in Chance News in 2004.] | |||
The Economist article mentions various techniques for counting deaths during a war: hospital death data, mortuary tallies and media reports, each producing different results. The Lancet study claims that the true figure is much higher than estimated by these other techniques. | |||
The Economist summaries the Lancet article's technique as one based on random sampling: | |||
<blockquote> | |||
selecting small numbers of people at random allows statisticians to say something about the whole population. ... there is no reliable census data in Iraq, truly random selection is impossible because the list from which this would take place is incomplete. So the researchers used a technique that is called clustering. | |||
</blockquote> | |||
The Economist article says that the researchers picked 47 neighbourhoods at random, each containing almost 40 households, and then surveyed all the people living in them. They asked people whether anyone had died since January 1st 2002 and what had caused their death. They also asked to see death certificates and 92% of the reported deaths were certified. | |||
They extrapolated the figures to reflect the national picture, saying Iraq's death rate had more than doubled since the invasion. | |||
By comparing the number of deaths before the fall of Saddam Hussein (5.5 per 1,000) to the latest figures (13.3 per 1,000 people a year), the authors claim an excess 650,000 deaths as a result of the invasion, which is 2.5 percent of the Iraqi population. | |||
The Economist cautions readers that data from individuals within a cluster are highly correlated so the 650,000 lies in the middle of a wide range: 390,000 and 943,000. | |||
The lead author suggested the media should not get too focused on the 655,000 number. | |||
[http://www.cnn.com/2006/WORLD/meast/10/11/iraq.deaths/ US President George Bush] quickly dismissed the findings. | |||
<blockquote> | |||
I don't consider it a credible report. Neither does Gen. (George) Casey (referring to the top ranking U.S. military official in Iraq) and neither do Iraqi officials.<br> | |||
The methodology is pretty well discredited. | |||
</blockquote> | |||
The lead author defended his team's methodology, saying it was the standard used in developing countries to survey for HIV and other major health issues. | |||
===Questions=== | |||
* The survey teams consisted of two male and two female medical doctors fluent in Arabic and English. Does this add to the credibility of the figures? The results were rejected by the US president and one of his generals, does that detract from the credibility of the figures? | |||
* The Lancet's figures could be cross checked by comparing them to other public surveillance mechanisms. For example, UN reports sum Baghdad morgue and Ministry of Health data. This suggests that less than a tenth of Iraqis who were killed or injured, according to the Lancet paper, were noticed by other sources. How might the difference in estimates be explained? Is it plausible that biases in the Lancet suvery methodology or in the other competing data sources, or both, could account for magnitude of the differences in the estimates? | |||
===Further reading=== | |||
* [http://i.a.cnn.net/cnn/2006/images/10/11/human.cost.of.war.pdf The Human Cost of the War in Iraq A Mortality Study, 2002-2006,] (leader Gilbert Burnham) Bloomberg School of Public Health, Johns Hopkins University and School of Medicine, Al Mustansiriya University, Baghdad, Iraq. | |||
** [http://www.iraqbodycount.net/press/pr14.php Reality checks: some responses to the latest Lancet estimates,] Hamit Dardagan, John Sloboda, and Josh Dougherty, 16 Oct 2006. Sceptical comments on the Lancet paper from an anti-war website ([http://reports.iraqbodycount.org/d/lancet_reality_checks.pdf pdf] copy). This private British-based [http://www.iraqbodycount.net/ website] estimates civilians reported killed by military intervention in Iraq at 44,190 (min) to 49,068 (max), based on online media counts and eyewitness accounts. In particular, this paper draws five conclusions from the Lancet paper and then criticises each of them in turn. | |||
* [http://www.thelancet.com/journals/lancet/article/PIIS0140673606694919/fulltext Mortality after the 2003 invasion of Iraq: a cross-sectional cluster sample survey,] Burnham G, Lafta R, Doocy S, Roberts L, The Lancet - Vol. 368, Issue 9545, 21 October 2006, pages 1421-1428. | |||
* [http://www.dartmouth.edu/~chance/chance_news/current_news/current.html#item7 Counting the casualties; the Iraq war,] CHANCE News 13.06, November 2, 2004 to December 31, 2004. The earlier Chance News article on this topic. | |||
** [http://www.economist.com/science/displayStory.cfm?story_id=3352814 Counting the casualties,] The Economist, Nov 4th 2004. The earlier study as reported by The Economist. | |||
** [http://www.iraqanalysis.org/local/041101lancetpmos.html The UK government’s response] to that earlier study, refuting the figures quoted back then. | |||
**[http://online.wsj.com/public/article/SB112309371679604061-EAfVPB24lX6gSz3wkK_gg0HtRvU_20060804.html?mod=tff_main_tff_top Counting the civilian dead in Iraq]. Carl Bialik comments on the earlier study in this installment of his [http://blogs.wsj.com/numbersguy/ The Numbers Guy] column in the Wall Street Journal, August 5, 2005. | |||
* There is now an R package on this topic - [http://cran.dsmirror.nl/src/contrib/Descriptions/lancet.iraqmortality.html lancet.iraqmortality: Surveys of Iraq Mortality Published in The Lancet.] | |||
** In particular, there is a nice vignette <em>[http://cran.dsmirror.nl/doc/vignettes/lancet.iraqmortality/mortality.pdf The Lancet Surveys of Mortality in Iraq,]</em> which includes a statistical analysis. | |||
** This package includes the following sources, for further reading: | |||
*** <em>[http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Lancet_surveys_of_mortality_before_and_after_the_2003_invasion_of_Iraq Mortality before and after the 2003 invasion of Iraq cluster sample survey,]</em> by Les Roberts, Riyadh Lafta, Richard Garfield, Jamal Khudhairi, and Gilbert Burnham. The Lancet, October 29, 2004. | |||
*** <em>Mortality after the 2003 invasion of Iraq: a cross-sectional cluster sample survey,</em> by Gilbert Burnham, Riyadh Lafta, Shannon Doocy, and Les Roberts. The Lancet, October 11, 2006. | |||
*** [http://crookedtimber.org/2004/11/11/lancet-roundup-and-literature-review crookedtimber.org] | |||
*** [http://scienceblogs.com/deltoid/lancetiraq/ scienceblogs.com] | |||
* The [http://news.nationaljournal.com National Journal] offers a detailed article on the issues covered above, nicely summarising the story to date and criticizes some of the authors' motives. | |||
** [http://news.nationaljournal.com/articles/databomb/index.htm Data bomb,] National Journal, 4th January 2008, Neil Munro and Carl M. Cannon. |
Latest revision as of 19:15, 24 February 2012
September 28, 2006 to November 1, 2006
Quotation
You may end up with a different math, but you're entitled to your math. I'm entitled to THE math.
Note: Karl Rove is the White House Deputy Chief of Staff. He was comparing the 68 polls a week that he reads with those that moderator Robert Siegle reads from the media.
Forsooth
These two Forsooths are from the October RRS NEWS.
Long-term, serious smokers have a 50% chance of dying.
Guardian Weekend
1 April 2006, p32.
The IOC Coordination Commission were told that 80 per cent of the land had already been acquired. London Mayor Ken Livingstone added that he was hoping that, by the time the public enquiry starts at the end of next month, four-fifths of the land would have been acquired.
Radio Oxford news report
20 April 2006
A car talk puzzle revisited
In Chance News 20 we asked for the answer to the following car talk puzzle (Week of 08-23-04):
The bullet holes were all over the place on the R.A.F. planes -- in the wings
and the fuselage, and seemingly distributed randomly on the undersides. So, where did the R.A.F. mathematician recommend extra armor, to save future
missions?
Car Talk gave the following answer:
A nameless mathematician crawled underneath the planes and looked at where the
bullet holes were on the underside. They were all over the place as you might expect -- in the wings and the fuselage, and seemingly distributed randomly on the undersides. He studied hundreds of planes, took pictures, drew a number of sketches -- and then he made his recommendation.
His recommendation very simply was to armor plate the unhit areas that the returning planes had in common. When he surveyed the undersides of these planes, he noticed that there were a few spots that all of them had in common that had no bullet holes. And he had to assume that the ones that hadn't returned hadbullet holes in those locations. They were in the English Channel someplace.
Reader Mike Cox wrote us that the mathematician was the famous statistician Abraham Wald and gave the following references for Wald's work: "A Method of Estimating Plane Vulnerability Based on Damage of Survivors, Abraham Wald, Center for Naval Analyses, 423, July 1980. and "Abraham Wald's Work on Aircraft Survivability, Marc Mangel;Fancisco J. Samaniego, Journal of the American Statistical Association,Vol. 79, No. 386, pp. 259-267.
The Car Talk story was discussed in "A selection of selection anomalies," Chance Magazine, Vol. 11, No. 2, Spring 1998, pp. 3-8, Howard Wainer, Samuel Palmer, and Eric T. Bradlow and we reviewed this article in Chance news 7.05 so we should have remembered this story. It is also discussed in Howard Wainer's recent book "Graphic Discovery: A Trout in the Milk and Other Visual Adventures" and on the Digital Roan Blog.
When we looked the Wald references we were surprised to find that they did not include the Car Talk story or the sketches often mentioned in discussing this story. However, as the title suggests, Wald did discuss ways to assess the chance of a plane being shot down by hits at various parts of a plane, so it is plausible that he might have recommended armor plating only the unhit areas that the returning planes had in common. If anyone knows a reference where he made this recommendation we would ask that you let us know about this. However as a wise man said: "Facts shouldn't get in the way of a good story."
Here is a brief sketch of what Wald does in the Center for Naval Analyses report. Wald assumes that we have the following data for planes participating in combat:
(1) The total number N of planes participating in combat.
(2) For any integer i (i = 0,1,2,...) the number of planes that received exactly i hits but have not been downed, i.e., have returned from combat.
The data in (2) is an example of missing data since the corresponding information is not known for the planes that do not return.
Wald assumes that the probability that a plane will be shot down does not depend on the number of previous non-destructive hits. In his first chapter he shows how, despite the missing data, we can estimate the probability that a plane is shot down by the i'th hit. In a later chapter he divides the plane into four equal areas and shows how to estimate the probability that a plane is downed by a single hit for each of the four areas. This allows him to compare the vulnerability of these areas. He illustrates this by the following example:
400 planes go on a bombing mission, 359 return. Of these, 240 were not hit, 68 had one it, 29 had two hits, 12 had three hits, and 10 had four hits.
His analysis shows that the probabilities of being downed by a single hit in each of the four areas is given in the following table:
Part | Probability of being downed by a single hit. |
Entire plane | .15 |
Engines | .39 |
Fuselage | .05 |
Fuel system | .15 |
Other parts | .02 |
Wald writes:
Thus for the observed data of this hypothetical example, the engine area is the most vulnerable in the sense that a hit there is most likely to down the plane. The fuselage has a relatively low vulnerability.
Wald remarks that this method can be used as a guide for locating protection armor and can be used to make a prediction of the esitimated loss in future missions.
The article by Mangel and Samaniego gives a good account of Wald's work and shows how to apply more recent statistical techniques to Wald's problems. Their article is followed by interesting comments by James Berger which in turn is followed by a rejoinder from Mangel and Samaniego. This rejoinder includes the following interesting comment:
A number of people have asked whether Wald's work has actually been used. We do not know whether it was used during World War II, although it was produced early enough in the war to have been available. We do know that during the Vietnam War, analysts at the Operations Evaluation Group of the Center for Naval Analyses used Wald's techniques to study the survivability of the A-4 aircraft. Their analysis led to structural modifications that improved the A-4's survivability.
Submitted by Laurie Snell
Probability theory is not all that useful
Don’t box yourself in when making decisions, John Kay, Financial Times, 22 August 2006.
In this article, John Kay, a weekly columnist for the Financial Times, outlines a variation on the Monty Hall problem, to highlight that human minds are not well adapted to dealing with issues of probability.
Suppose there are only two boxes and one contains twice as much money as the other. When you choose one, you are shown that it contains £100. Will you stick with your original choice, or switch to the other box?
Kay shows that it is easy to apply this problem to real situations:
Anyone who has changed jobs, bought a house or planned a merger has encountered a version of the two-box game; keep what you know, or go for an uncertain alternative.
In this game, players can lose only £50 but might gain £100 and they have no way of judging whether the £50 loss is more or less likely than the £100 gain.
Decision theory predicts an expected gain of £25 from an equal chance of winning £100 or losing £50. But many people dislike the prospect of losing £50 more than they like the prospect of gaining £100. Reflecting his economic background, Kay goes on to speculate that this irrationality may explain why the equity premium in finance is so high – volatile assets need to show much higher returns to compensate for the pain of frequently seeing small losses.
Kay then outlines what he calls the 'fallacy of large numbers'
If you accepted 100 gambles like this, you are virtually certain to end up with a substantial gain. But, you may say, I am not playing this game 100 times. I am only playing it once and you cannot guarantee a gain in a single trial. That is true, but it illustrates “the fallacy of large numbers”. On the 100th trial, you are in the same position as someone who is offered the chance to do it once. So you should not do it the 100th time. But then you should not do it the 99th time, or the 98th – or the first.
He concludes that probability theory works well for a limited class of problems, but the real world is much more open-ended and there is usually fundamental uncertainty about both the nature of the outcomes and the process that gives rise to them.
Questions
- Kay claims that 'the message of both the original Monty Hall problem and of this one is that, even in very simple cases, it is impossible to be certain that a particular mathematical representation of a real problem is a correct description. ... For people in business who rely on models and for people in financial services who must choose between boxes with uncertain contents every day, that is a disturbing conclusion.' Do you agree with his views? If yes, what might it imply for the teaching of probability?
- Do you agree with Kay's comment that many people dislike the propect of losing £50 more than they like the prospect of gaining £100? This touches on the topic of behavioural economics, in particular loss aversion according to prospect theory - given a choice between risky outcomes, we suffer about two times as much for losses as we enjoy comparable gains. This has become a popular topic for study in recent years, especially since Daniel Kahneman was awarded a Nobel prize in economics 'for having integrated insights from psychological research into economic science, especially concerning human judgment and decision-making under uncertainty'. Does this comment help to resolve this paradox or is it irrelevant?
- Repeating the game many times, increases the chance of achieving positive expected payoff. What hidden assumptions are being made here? (If a few more zeros were added to the payoffs, would your attitude be different?) Is there any merit in his 'fallacy of large numbers'? What is it about the 99th attempt that makes it different to the first attempt?
- To benefit from the irrationality of the equity premium, Kay suggests to stop looking at share prices so often, so, in the long run, you will get the benefit of the higher return without the pain of observing volatility. Is there any merit in this suggestion? Does it suggest that rational investors, facing the same problem but with different time horizons, can logically reach very different conclusions?
Further reading
- The topic in this article (and the next one) is often referred to as the envelope paradox(s) which have been discussed in previous issues of Chance News going back to 1992. For example, Chance News 9.09 in the discussion qustions says 'A much more mysterious envelope paradox is the following: I put two distinct numbers a and b in an envelope. You pick one of the numbers at random. Show that you can decide if you have the bigger or smaller number with a probability greater than 1/2 of being correct. The envelope paradoxes are discussed in Chapter 4, examples 4.28 and 4.29 of the on-line probability book Introduction to Probability, Charles M. Grinstead and J. Laurie Snell, American Mathematical Society.
- There are several webpages devoted to this difficult paradox. For example, Amos Storkey offers a Bayesian solution and logician Raymond Smullyan claims that the paradox can be restated without involving probability in his book Satan, Cantor and Infinity and Other Mind-boggling Puzzles. He does this by proving two contradictory propositions:
- "Proposition 1. The amount that you will gain, if you do gain, is greater than the amount you will lose, if you do lose.
- "Proposition 2. The amounts are the same."
Submitted by John Gavin.
Intuition is better than maths
The maths may be simple but intuition is more usefull, John Kay, Financial Times 29 August 2006.
In the two-box problem (see the 'Probability theory is not all that useful' article above), that puzzle offers you a choice of two boxes, one containing more money than the other. Once you have made a decision, you are shown what is in your preferred box. Do you stick with your original choice, or switch?
Kay claims a knowledge of probabilities seems to be a hindrance rather than a help because, with no other information, it seems no rational decision can be made. In this follow-up article, Kay advocates a strategy that seems better than always switching or always sticking, one that beats random choice even in a situation of almost total ignorance.
Before the game starts, focus on a sum of money. It does not matter what the amount is – say, £100. The 'threshold strategy' is to switch if the box you choose contains less than £100 and to stick if it contains more. The threshold strategy gives you a better-than-even chance of getting the larger sum. It does so for any value of the threshold you choose.
If both boxes have less than £100, or more than £100, then the probability that you get the larger sum from your random choice remains one-half. But if one box has less than £100 and the other has more than £100, adopting the threshold strategy makes sure you get the larger sum. Since there is at least a possibility that the amounts in the boxes lie in this range, the threshold strategy must increase your chance of winning.
Kay suggests that there is little benefit to choosing a threshold that is very high or very low, claiming that if you have some idea, however vague, about the range of possible contents, you can tweak the threshold strategy to your advantage. He also suggests choosing a threshold in the range of sums of money that would make a real difference to you. For example, if £20,000 would not transform your life but £50,000 would, then go for £50,000.
While admitting that the logic behind this solution is not straightforward but he claims that, intuitively, it makes sense. He claims that in real-life problems we typically adopt the principle of being realistic while looking for something that will make a difference.
In the version of the two-box problem, in the previous Chance article, where you had the additional information that one box contained twice as much money as the other, there seemed always to be an argument for switching; the potential gain is always twice the seemingly equally likely potential loss. But this conclusion is wrong. Once more, intuition runs ahead of our mathematical understanding, he concludes.
Questions
- Do you agree with the solution outlined in this article?
- Do you think Kay is right to be so skeptical about probability?
Submitted by John Gavin
Comments on Kay's articles
In his first article, Kay discusses the infamous two-box or two-envelope problem. This problem has a long history which you can find at Wikipedia here.
Here is the way this problem is described in the Grinstead-Snell probability book. Two-envelopes each contain a certain amount of money. One envelope is given to Ali and the other to Baba and they are told that one envelope contains twice as much money as the other. However, neither knows who has the larger prize. Before anyone has opened their envelope, Ali is asked if she would like to trade her envelope with Baba. She reasons as follows: Assume that the amount in my envelope is x. If I switch, I will end up with x/2 with probability 1/2, and 2x with probability 1/2. If I were given the opportunity to play this game many times, and if I were to switch each time, I would, on average, get
This is greater than my average winnings if I didn't switch.
Of course, Baba is presented with the same opportunity and reasons in the same way to conclude that he too would like to switch. So they switch and each thinks that his/her net worth just went up by 25%.
Since neither has yet opened any envelope, this process can be repeated and so again they switch. Now they are back with their original envelopes and yet they think that their fortune has increased 25% twice. By this reasoning, they could convince themselves that by repeatedly switching the envelopes, they could become arbitrarily wealthy. Clearly, something is wrong with the above reasoning, but where is the mistake?
Well, for one thing we have interpreted <math> \frac{5}{4}x</math> as the expected amount Ali will have if she switches. But x is a random variable, not a number, as would be required for an expected value.
To correctly compute the expected value we have to know something about how the numbers x, and 2x were put in the envelopes. Assume that we toss a coin. If heads turns up x is put in envelope 1 and 2x in envelope 2. if tails turn up 2x is put in envelope 1 and x in envelope 2. This satisfies the condition that Ali and Bali have no idea which number they have but they know that one number is twice the other number. Then since each envelope has x or 2x as the result of the toss of a coin the expected amount in either envelope is 1/2(x) + 1/2(2x) = 3/2x. So why switch?
In the second article Kay seems to be considering the same problem but his description fits better with the second envelope paradox which is credited to Thomas Cover: "Pick the largest number" in Communication and Computation, T. Cover and B. Gopinath, eds., Springer-Verlag, New York, 1987, p. 152.
In this problem you are given 2 envelopes in each of which there are a number, and these numbers are different.. You are asked to choose one of the envelopes and tell if you think you have the smaller or the larger of the two numbers. It would seem that you could not do better than having a 50% chance of being correct but the surprising thing is that you can do better.
To do this you choose a number according to a normal distribution with mean 0 or 1. Actually any distribution would do as long as all numbers are possible. Cover calls this number the splitting number T.
If the number you chose was less than T then you say that you have the smaller number. If it is greater than T you say that you have the bigger number. Then you can show that if T is between the two numbers in the envelope you are sure to be correct and if not you still have a 50% chance of being correct. Since there is a positive probability that T will be between the two numbers you have a greater than 50% chance of being correct.
Kay has the right idea for the solution to this problem but he chooses a specific number for T so he will not be able to be right with probability greater than .5 if the numbers were put in such a way that they must be bigger than T.
Returning to the original problem, recall that Ali was allowed to what number was in her box. Thus while she cannot get a 25% increase by switching, by using Cover's strategy she can decide whether to switch or not in a way that will give her better than a 50% chance of ending up with 2x as Kay suggests in his second article.
Submitted by Laurie Snell.
You're Only as Old As You Think You Are
Gina Kolata is the New York Times health writer and by all accounts is at least several decades under 70 but that doesn't stop her from writing about geriatrics. Her October 5, 2006 article is entitled "Old but Not Frail: A Matter of Heart and Head." According to her experts, "you're only as old as you think you are. Rigorous studies are now showing that seeing, or hearing, gloomy nostrums about what it is like to be old can make people walk more slowly, hear and remember less well, and even affect their cardiovascular systems. Positive images of aging have the opposite effects. The constant message that old people are expected to be slow and weak and forgetful is not a reason for the full-blown frailty syndrome. But it may help push people along that path."
An epidemiologist at the National Institute on Aging, Eleanor Simonsick, "recruited 3,075 apparently healthy people in their 70's who said they could walk a quarter of a mile with no trouble and climb a flight of stairs. Each was asked to walk up and down a corridor 10 times, for a distance of a quarter mile, maintaining their pace and not stopping to rest." Although the average age of those who could and those who could not were identically 73, "A quarter of them could not do it." By the end of two years, "a third of the group that could walk the quarter mile said they were beginning to have difficulty."
These depressing results for those of us over 70 may be found in the May 3, 2006 issue of The Journal of the American Medical Association; "being unable to walk a quarter mile within five minutes portended troubles. For each minute beyond five, the risk of dying in the next four years increased by a third, the risk of having a heart attack increased by 20 percent, and the risk of having a disability increased by half." Further, "Those who took more than six minutes for the quarter-mike walk had the same risk of dying or having heart attack as those who could not walk the distance at all, and the effect was independent of age."
Despite beginning and ending her article with a focus on how elderly people's physical health depends on what others think of them, Kolata then does an about-face by posing a cause and effect question relating physical exercise: rather than frailty causing the inability to walk, "Could teaching people to walk further and faster prevent their growing so weak they could hardly walk?" A director of the National Institute on Aging claims that such a program to make more people mobile would save billions of dollars.
Discussion
1. Reconcile the following two phrases: (1) You are only as old as you think you are, and (2) Act your age.
2. A professor at the University of Pittsburgh states, " I would say all 100-year-old people are frail. Most 90-year-olds are frail. And some 80-year-olds are frail." Speculate on the solidness of her data.
3. What physical aspects of your life depend on your image as seen by others?
4. In your view, does frailty cause inability to walk, or does inability to walk cause frailty? Give some other examples of cause and effect where it is not clear which is the cause and which is the effect.
Submitted by Paul Alper
Conflicts of Interest
An aspect of statistical literacy that doesn't get enough appreciation is that of conflict of interest; it leads to surprising if not downright unbelievable results. The Washington Post had two articles which illustrate the concept. Shankar Vedantum on October 3, 2006 reported that "Schizophrenia patients do as well, or perhaps even better, on older psychiatric drugs compared with newer and far costlier medications" according to a study involving 227 randomly assigned patients reported in the Archives of General Psychiatry. This study was funded by the British government as opposed to the many other studies funded by the pharmaceutical industry which, of course, has a vested interest along with an alarmingly aggressive marketing arm.
Peter Jones is the leader of the government study; when searching for the appropriate word to characterize the lack of superiority of more expensive, newer drugs as portrayed in previous studies, he said, "'Duped' is not right...We were beguiled" by the previous studies. Jones further reflected on the importance of trusting data, rather than one's own judgment: "Sometimes the compass tells you go straight in front of you, but you somehow know it is wrong and that north is behind you...I have learned to follow the compass."
Annys Shin on October 5, 2006 in her column, The Checkout, deals with The Salt Conspiracy. "We've all been told to be dubious of studies paid for by Big Tobacco. Lately, we've learned it's hard to find an expert on depression or schizophrenia who isn't getting paid by Big Pharma. And now, CPSI [Center for Science in the Public Interest] is telling us, we have Big Salt." The Journal of the College of Nutrition had a supplement a few months previous claiming that salt is not bad for you, an argument that astonished many. Turns out the editor of the supplement, Dr. Alexander G. Logan, is, as alleged by CPSI, a "paid consultant to the salt industry" and failed to disclose his industry connections. "The articles were also not peer reviewed." In an epilogue to the Shin's article, an irate email from Logan to Shin states "I hold no ownership in any business related to the food or salt industries. I do not accept fees or honoraria for any consultative advice that I provide related to nutrition or salt."
A common conflict of interest exists at Division 1A universities. There the clash is between the academic and the athletic. The result is the so-called "student athlete." Naturally, many of these athletes should never be in college. "After high school, I thought I was done with school," said Gary Russell, a star running back with the University of Minnesota who flunked out of the university. According to the Minneapolis Star Tribune of October 2, 2006, "He earned only 28 credits out of a possible 51 and had a cumulative grade-point average of 1.829." This overstates his GPA because "He did receive three A's in Football coaching, Weight Training and Beginning Tennis." This is an excerpt from a much larger article which indicates that among the Big Ten schools, the University of Minnesota's "Graduation Success Rate" or GSR is not only last in football, but also in "men's basketball, women's basketball, men's cross country/track, men's golf, men's hockey and softball." Despite this dismal result, the head football coach and the men's athletic director each recently received a large raise in pay. The base salary for the latter is now at $315 thousand per year and for the former, $1.65 million per year; without resorting to any in-depth research, most statisticians earn far less. Those numbers do not include the usual perks bestowed on coaches and athletic directors. And, oh yes, the legislature voted this past session to build a new football stadium for its beloved Gophers. Naming rights belong to a local bank who in return for the $35 million contribution get to monopolize ATM devices on campus along with the privilege of accessing the student data base.
Discussion
1. The pharmaceutical industry has an obvious axe to grind. Does the British Government? The U.S. Food and Drug Administration?
2. The history of salt is fascinating and only in the modern era is salt inexpensive and prevalent. Mark Kurlansky is the author of Salt: A World History and makes for a good read.
3. Dr. Logan vigorously denies any monetary connection with the salt industry. Do you tend to side with him or with CPSI?
4. Are you surprised that Russell received the three As mentioned? What effect on the football team's performance will result from a new stadium?
Submitted by Paul Alper
The odds of dying
What are the odds of dying?, The (US) National Safety Council website.
Ways to Go, National Geographic, Siobhan Roth, August 2006.
Recent statistics from the National Safety Council reveal the most likely way to die, over the lifetime of a US resident. So this article's objective is to answer commonly-asked questions from the media such as, what are the odds of being killed by lightning? or what are the chances of dying in a plane crash?
It includes common causes of death, like car accidents, as well as large scale catastrophes, such as earthquakes. For example, motorbike riding is more risky than playing with fireworks.
Questions
- The National Safety Council website presents the data in tabular as well as graphical form. Which form of presentation do you think makes it easier to interpret the data?
- In the previous edition on Chance, a similar article, Risk perceptions ranked different ways of dying in tabular form. Is a ranked table easier to read? Is it always more appropriate for this kind of data?
- In the graph below, the probabilities appear to be proportional to the area of the circles. Is a two-dimensional, area-based scale appropriate to display on one-dimensional data like probabilities? Why use circles?
- The National Safety Council website states that these odds are statistical averages over the whole U.S. population and do not necessarily reflect the chances of death for a particular person from a particular external cause. What factors might cause an individual's odds to deviate from the average?
- The odds are based on data from 2003. Why might the odds change more over time for some categories more than others?
Submitted by John Gavin.
Death and taxes - 2007 edition
Death and taxes - 2007 edition, by Jesse Bachman, thebudgetgraph.com, 2006.
Amazing graph of how US income tax gets spent, BoingBoing website, Sep 18, 2006.
Continuing from the previous article with the theme of visualising data: an on-line, interactive graph neatly visualises how the US federal government spends its income taxes.
Clicking on this image will open up a larger but static version of the graph. Whereas the original, interactive website version allows users to zoom in on different parts and to pan around the graph to see its full resolution, which isn't available with the static graphs associated with this article.
The data is broken into its constituent parts using a tree (or spider map) layout, with the area of each node on the tree representing the amount for each expenditure item.
Jesse Bachman, the graph's designer, says
the graph is the star here, it puts things into perspective. Its purpose is to generate questions.
Following comments from the public, the author later supplemented the original Death and Taxes graph with a simplier graph (shown below) showing mandatory spending as well, which adds some perspective.
Questions
- Assuming you can work with the on-line version, in order to zoom in, does the graph put the data into perspective, especially the complexity and inter-connectedness of the various items? For example, how does the national debt compare to other items? Does the total budget shown in the second graph offer a more informative perspective because it is less granular than the first graph?
- Is the area of each node proportional to the magnitude of that item? What alternative relationships might be used to better visualise this information?
- Do the various images within the graph improve its appearance or distract from the underlying data? Can you think of other ways to further improve the graph?
- How well do you think the graph is researched and justified via supporting materials. What additional material would you like to see?
- Can you find your favourite government department easily, such as the spending on science research? e.g. why is the National Science Foundation shown under military or national security related.
Futher reading
- You can buy a poster ($24 plus $4.95 shipping to anywhere in the US) or send one to the US congress for ten dollars.
- This impressive animated film by graphic designer Nigel Holmes describes the relative sizes of the US surplus and debt.
- See this Chance News article for links to the latest (2009) graph.
Submitted by John Gavin.
Alzheimer's
The medical moral of the story is simple: stay healthy so you don't need drugs. The statistical moral of the study is two-fold: (1) go to the original source instead of relying on what journalists write and (2) make sure that the right experiment is being done. The New England Journal of Medicine article of October 12, 2006 (Volume 355: 1525-1538 Number 15) entitled "Effectiveness of Atypical Antipsychotic Drugs in Patients with Alzheimer's Disease" received a fair amount of puzzling press review. The AP dispatch said "Symptoms did improve in about 30 percent of patients taking the drugs, as well as in 21 percent of those getting a placebo, partly because symptoms can naturally wax and wane." With 421 patients in the study and ignoring multiple comparisons (three drugs and a placebo), a quick calculation yields a p-value of .032 which is less than the magical .05 so it would seem that statistical significance was achieved. Yet, regarding clinical significance, the AP headline was "Anti-psychotic drugs don't ease dementia." Likewise, the headline for HealthDay's Amanda Gardner says "Antipsychotics No Better Than Placebo For Alzheimer's Patients." The headline for Denise Gellene's article in the Los Angeles Times was "Alzheimer's antipsychotic drugs 'are not the answer for most,' report says."
It turns out that while 421 patients were enrolled in 42 different sites (!), 82% quit their medications due to lack of efficacy, intolerability and other reasons; in short, these powerful drugs have unpleasant side effects such as death. According to an accompanying editorial in the NEJM by Jason Karlawish, this clinical trial is the right experiment as opposed to previous clinical trials involving drugs for Alzheimer's. Those studies have outcomes which "are measured at multiple time points" accruing "a large volume of data." These approaches increase "the likelihood that any change measured will be statistically, though not necessarily clinically, significant. Clearly, these designs are particularly valuable to companies seeking an FDA label or reprints of reports to distribute to clinicians."
Karlawish writes, "The primary end point in the study by Schneider et al. is an accurate reflection of a clinical event: the decision to change treatment because the patient's condition is worsening or not improving sufficiently."
Discussion
1. The NEJM article had 13 authors, 12 of whom listed "potential conflicts of interest." The only one not listed as having a potential conflict of interest was the person without a M.D. or Ph.D. degree. Speculate what this implies.
2. Define statistical significance. Define clinical significance. Does one imply the other?
3. Despite the negative results of this clinical trial, because some patients benefited, the lead author said, "The message from this study cannot be that the drugs are not useful." Is this a scientific or a religious belief?
4. All of the above refers to "Phase I." "Phase II" was not reported on in this article. In Phase II, those patients still willing to be randomly assigned "under double-blind conditions to receive one of the antipsychotic drugs to which they were not initially assigned" or to receive a drug not studied in Phase I. Why is this a good idea statistically? Why might this not be such a good idea for a patient?
Submitted by Paul Alper.
The human cost of war
Calculating casualties - The human cost of war in Iraq, The Economist, Oct 12th 2006.
A recent statistical study in the Lancet, a UK medical journal, claims that many more Iraqis have died in recent years than was previously thought, over 650,000 excess deaths. This is a follow-up study to a 2004 Lancet article on the same topic that was previously discussed in Chance News in 2004.
The Economist article mentions various techniques for counting deaths during a war: hospital death data, mortuary tallies and media reports, each producing different results. The Lancet study claims that the true figure is much higher than estimated by these other techniques. The Economist summaries the Lancet article's technique as one based on random sampling:
selecting small numbers of people at random allows statisticians to say something about the whole population. ... there is no reliable census data in Iraq, truly random selection is impossible because the list from which this would take place is incomplete. So the researchers used a technique that is called clustering.
The Economist article says that the researchers picked 47 neighbourhoods at random, each containing almost 40 households, and then surveyed all the people living in them. They asked people whether anyone had died since January 1st 2002 and what had caused their death. They also asked to see death certificates and 92% of the reported deaths were certified.
They extrapolated the figures to reflect the national picture, saying Iraq's death rate had more than doubled since the invasion. By comparing the number of deaths before the fall of Saddam Hussein (5.5 per 1,000) to the latest figures (13.3 per 1,000 people a year), the authors claim an excess 650,000 deaths as a result of the invasion, which is 2.5 percent of the Iraqi population. The Economist cautions readers that data from individuals within a cluster are highly correlated so the 650,000 lies in the middle of a wide range: 390,000 and 943,000. The lead author suggested the media should not get too focused on the 655,000 number.
US President George Bush quickly dismissed the findings.
I don't consider it a credible report. Neither does Gen. (George) Casey (referring to the top ranking U.S. military official in Iraq) and neither do Iraqi officials.
The methodology is pretty well discredited.
The lead author defended his team's methodology, saying it was the standard used in developing countries to survey for HIV and other major health issues.
Questions
- The survey teams consisted of two male and two female medical doctors fluent in Arabic and English. Does this add to the credibility of the figures? The results were rejected by the US president and one of his generals, does that detract from the credibility of the figures?
- The Lancet's figures could be cross checked by comparing them to other public surveillance mechanisms. For example, UN reports sum Baghdad morgue and Ministry of Health data. This suggests that less than a tenth of Iraqis who were killed or injured, according to the Lancet paper, were noticed by other sources. How might the difference in estimates be explained? Is it plausible that biases in the Lancet suvery methodology or in the other competing data sources, or both, could account for magnitude of the differences in the estimates?
Further reading
- The Human Cost of the War in Iraq A Mortality Study, 2002-2006, (leader Gilbert Burnham) Bloomberg School of Public Health, Johns Hopkins University and School of Medicine, Al Mustansiriya University, Baghdad, Iraq.
- Reality checks: some responses to the latest Lancet estimates, Hamit Dardagan, John Sloboda, and Josh Dougherty, 16 Oct 2006. Sceptical comments on the Lancet paper from an anti-war website (pdf copy). This private British-based website estimates civilians reported killed by military intervention in Iraq at 44,190 (min) to 49,068 (max), based on online media counts and eyewitness accounts. In particular, this paper draws five conclusions from the Lancet paper and then criticises each of them in turn.
- Mortality after the 2003 invasion of Iraq: a cross-sectional cluster sample survey, Burnham G, Lafta R, Doocy S, Roberts L, The Lancet - Vol. 368, Issue 9545, 21 October 2006, pages 1421-1428.
- Counting the casualties; the Iraq war, CHANCE News 13.06, November 2, 2004 to December 31, 2004. The earlier Chance News article on this topic.
- Counting the casualties, The Economist, Nov 4th 2004. The earlier study as reported by The Economist.
- The UK government’s response to that earlier study, refuting the figures quoted back then.
- Counting the civilian dead in Iraq. Carl Bialik comments on the earlier study in this installment of his The Numbers Guy column in the Wall Street Journal, August 5, 2005.
- There is now an R package on this topic - lancet.iraqmortality: Surveys of Iraq Mortality Published in The Lancet.
- In particular, there is a nice vignette The Lancet Surveys of Mortality in Iraq, which includes a statistical analysis.
- This package includes the following sources, for further reading:
- Mortality before and after the 2003 invasion of Iraq cluster sample survey, by Les Roberts, Riyadh Lafta, Richard Garfield, Jamal Khudhairi, and Gilbert Burnham. The Lancet, October 29, 2004.
- Mortality after the 2003 invasion of Iraq: a cross-sectional cluster sample survey, by Gilbert Burnham, Riyadh Lafta, Shannon Doocy, and Les Roberts. The Lancet, October 11, 2006.
- crookedtimber.org
- scienceblogs.com
- The National Journal offers a detailed article on the issues covered above, nicely summarising the story to date and criticizes some of the authors' motives.
- Data bomb, National Journal, 4th January 2008, Neil Munro and Carl M. Cannon.